An ‘Old’ Us and a ‘New’ Them. Introduzione Enciclopedica allo Studio del Diritto by G.D. Romagnosi

Sara Parini Vincenti

Università degli Studi di Milano

sara.parini@unimi.it

Abstract: Gian Domenico Romagnosi’s contribution to the restructuring of legal studies in Italy – a reform unfurled through plans and bills, namely the Piano di istruzione legale (Legal Education Plan) and Progetto di Regolamento degli Studi Legali (Project for the Regulation of Legal Studies) and, from a legislative point of view, through the formation of the Regolamento per gli studi Pratici Legali (Regulations for Practical Legal Studies), as well as the creation of three Postgraduate Schools – culminating in the drafting of an unpublished textbook entitled Introduzione enciclopedica allo studio del diritto. his work still strove to collect and explain knowledge: as such, it was a sort of manifestation of the goals he had alluded to ten years earlier in Studio preparatorio alla Facoltà Politico Legale. His Introduzione was meant to be just that: ‘introductory tool’ that could embrace the whole of legal knowledge, so that the elderly Professor could take stock of his educational ambitions and disseminate the epistemological views that he identified with in the new institutional climate. Romagnosi came to this subject matter late in life, having left behind the various forms of individualistic radicalism that had typified the revolutionary era and his encyclopedia seems to be an appropriate way to summarize his life’s work.

Keywords: Romagnosi, Introduzione enciclopledica allo studio del diritto, Legal Education Plan, Schools of law, Faculty of law, Uversities

Table of contents: 1. New courses and new goals for legal studies.2. Introduzione enciclopedica allo studio del diritto.3. Pure didactics or an ethical science?

1. New courses and new goals for legal studies.

Years ago, as part of the various initiatives organized by the Commission for the History of the Legal Profession, I examined Gian Domenico Romagnosi’s contribution to the restructuring of legal studies in Italy[1]. This reform unfurled through plans and bills, namely the Piano di istruzione legale (Legal Education Plan) and Progetto di Regolamento degli Studi Legali (Project for the Regulation of Legal Studies). From a legislative point of view, these efforts would lead to the formation of the Regolamento per gli studi Pratici Legali (Regulations for Practical Legal Studies), as well as the creation of three Postgraduate Schools[2].

In order to complete this analysis of Romagnosi’s teachings, I think that it would be interesting to cover some new ground and delve into his unpublished textbook entitled Introduzione enciclopedica allo studio del diritto (Encyclopedic) Introduction to the Study of Law)[3]. One of his later works, it was written after Romagnosi had been able to avoid trial forhigh treason and was left with no choice but to resort to teaching in private – a situation that would not last for long, however[4].

Romagnosi’s textbook took shape under circumstances that were much different than those surrounding his Saggio filosofico sull’istruzione pubblica legale (Philosophical Treatise on Public Legal Education)[5]. Indeed, it was after 1817, and the experience of instituting postgraduate schools had since been abandoned (having already been first discouraged and then definitively shelved by the Austrians)[6]. Nonetheless, his work still strove to collect and explain knowledge: as such, it was a sort of manifestation of the goals he had alluded to ten years earlier in Studio preparatorio alla Facoltà Politico Legale (Preliminary Study for the Faculty of Law and Political Science), a text that he held as a fundamental part of his plan to restructure Italian legal studies[7]. His Introduzione was meant to be just that: an ‘introductory tool’ that could illustrate “the intellectual laws and natural principles of the just”; that could embrace the whole of legal knowledge, so that the elderly Professor could take stock of his educational ambitions and disseminate the epistemological views that he identified with in the new institutional climate ushered in by the Concert of Europe[8].

It is common knowledge that in the aftermath of the Congress of Vienna, the education of state bureaucrats became a priority in the science of government: officials were to be properly educated in the ways of administration[9], namely as concerned the fulfillment of tasks, respect for order and adherence to protocol.

Napoleonic policy had opened up universities to a wider community[10] and introduced the value of praxis[11]: but the Austrian government cut all ties to that approach once public education fell under their control. In fact, they reorganized education[12] and gave rise to a society that revolved around a sense of duty[13]. In short, the regime change presented a series of challenges regarding how knowledge was to be organized; how the best individual talents could be attracted to – and have success in – legal studies; and how legal studies could become the foundation for building a sound bureaucracy made up of capable Beamten who were loyal to the cause.

One only had to look outside of France to realize that the tools were actually already in place. Indeed, it would not be until 1840 that the first introductory course commenced in Paris, «sous le titre plus convenable d’Introduction générale à l’étude du Droit»[14].

On the other hand, the German territories had already been moving in this direction for a long time. In terms of didactics, it suffices to mention Johan Stephan Pütter’s Neuer Versuch einer Juristischen Encyclopädie und Méthodologie: when it was published in 1757[15], it marked the first time that a specific nomenclature had been coined for an introductory course of an ‘encyclopedic’ nature. It was to be introduced into academies in order to facilitate an understanding of positive law («als Instrument zum Verständnis des positiven Rechts»)[16], as teaching of the subject had been lacking up to that point.

This introductory approach, or «εγκύκλιος παιδεία»[17], would soon be crossing borders thanks to the publication of a series of notable compendia[18] on the subject. Admittedly, the content of each publication varied a fair amount in these early stages, but the aim of each was clearly stated in the title[19]. Thus, Pütter’s course was able to expand beyond the German legal sciences to the Netherlands and Russia[20], and by the beginning of the following century, it would come to be recognized as part of university curricula in Vienna and Berlin.

Indeed, August Böckh, who was a professor at the University of Heidelberg and author of Encyklopädie und Methodologie der philologischen Wissenschaften, was involved with a comprehensive course during the Sommersemester in Brandenburg in 1811[21]; meanwhile, the Encyclopaedische-methodische Einleitung in der juristisch-politisch Studium by Albert von Hess was already making its way around the Austrian capital as early as 1810[22].

The Imperial-Royal Universities of Lombardy-Venetia also proceeded along the same lines: they established a core course that the Istruzione pel giorno 15 ottobre 1817
[23] purposely called Introduzione enciclopedica (Encyclopedic Introduction). The evocation of an ‘encyclopedic’ approach was an indicative choice[24], as the course’s systematic structure not only helped establish the theoretical foundations of jurisprudence as a science, but also set it apart from other branches of knowledge by defining its aims and its general principles[25].

The indefatigable Romagnosi was not to be excluded from the spirit of the times, as he too put together an unpublished textbook on the subject[26] for the students enrolled at his private school, and which can be dated to some time between 1818 and 1821[27].

Let us now take a closer look at that work.

2. Introduzione enciclopedica allo studio del diritto.

First and foremost, it must be stated that this was an unfinished work. Romagnosi’s manuscript is made up of just over sixty pages, which were neither reviewed nor corrected. What’s more, it is contained in two different folders numbered 25 n. 6 and 25 n. 7, which is only further evidence of the fact that much work had been left undone.

The first bundle – number 6 – contains a draft of the text with a title, and was probably a provisional outline for his lessons. Each sheet was used in its entirety (full-page) going from sheet 1 (the title of the work) to sheet 32. In addition to a general, introductory part, there are also sections dedicated to Diritto privato naturale (Private natural law) (8 sheets) and Diritti Classificativi (Classificatory rights) (4 sheets), before moving on to Convenzioni (Agreements) (6 sheets) and concluding with Acquisto di beni per causa di morte (Inheritance of property from the deceased).

The second bundle – number 7 – is more similar to an outline of a core course to be offered in a university setting. At first glance, it comes off as a work in progress: just half of each page was written on, and often only the front side of the sheet was used, while the margins are filled with notes, second thoughts, additions and digressions. Yet the subject matter is meatier, the content is more substantial and the titles he used are more far-reaching: such is the case with the sections on Convenzioni (Agreements) and Acquisto di beni per causa di morte (Inheritance of property from the deceased) (sheets 1-22), Contratti (Contracts) (after several blank pages, this section starts up again on sheet 33), Diritti e doveri di famiglia (Rights and duties of the family), and Dominio reale (Dominium) (sheet 80), which concludes Romagnosi’s writing.

In terms of content, given the circumstances under which the work was carried out, one would have expected a relatively discreet ‘lesson’ that shied away from proclamations of momentous change in the teaching of law in general, let alone in the specific case of Romagnosi’s own educational program[28]. All the more so considering the straightforward approach taken by the author and the didactic style he chose in drafting his work, which took the form of a back-and-forth dialogue between master and pupil.

On the contrary, however, Romagnosi’s Introduzione stood out from the mass of comprehensive (‘encyclopedic’) treatises that had been called for by the Austrian leadership in order to educate students of the newly-restructured Faculty of Law and Political Science. His clearly-defined program went beyond simply pointing out the correct approach to political and legal studies: it revealed the elderly Maestro’s still-burning desire to once again take up the reins of the methodological debate surrounding education, which had begun many years before under Napoleon.

The textbook’s distribution was limited to the cramped confines of a private school, and Romagnosi faced physical, political and economic difficulties. Yet despite these impediments, his work was able to address the key issues that needed to be dealt with – legal definitions first and foremost, but also the aim and definition of each branch of law – in support of the philosophical development of a new legal system. What’s more, his textbook also examined how to organize the individual components of such a system, and how to trace those components back to the general principles of private law, which could not exist without a society to define it.

Romagnosi also picked up on the basic criterion laid out by encyclopedists in the eighteenth century who had examined the relationship between natural and positive law, the organization of legal relationships within a state system, and the connections between history and philosophy; however, he did not cite any of the works heretofore mentioned, except for that of Zeiller, who was the subject of a university exam that students were expected to take.

The opening pages anticipate the need for a well-balanced and uniform reconstruction of legal science; they also lay out «what the Introduzione contains»[29].

Namely:

the exposition of all the branches of legal doctrines that may be needed to manage public affairs […] the branches into which these doctrines may be divided […][30] how many scientific branches rational doctrine can in turn be divided into […][31]

Yet Romagnosi was not content with offering simply an overview of the subject. He had a much more ambitious goal for the course: to lay the ethical and moral groundwork for the education of all «specialists working in the various branches that make up the tree of legal sciences»[32].

The philosophical nature of Romagnosi’s work is immediately apparent. In order to assign a role to the individual in a political community, one must start from none other than the method of deductive reasoning that is taught to the young, inexperienced minds of students. For this reason, simply learning by rote cannot be the end goal of education; on the contrary, the student must assimilate a few great principles that confer control «of justice to legal science […] and utility to Politics […]»[33]. Indeed,

The functions of a welfare state serve the immediate purpose of […] protecting and improving individuals […] it follows that the Government’s work comes down to EDUCATION on a large scale in order to promote [the] CIVILIZATION [of its society][34].

On the other hand, an individual’s purpose is brought out through his role within civil society (Diritto come facoltà utile – Law as a useful power, sheet 11v), which is no longer a place where individual subjectivities clash, but rather a community whose progress depends on the contributions of all of its members.

Romagnosi sought to distance himself from Zeiller’s social vision (sheet 12), which envisaged a community of «self-sufficient and independent people»; quite the opposite, Romagnosi called for «a mutual union of individuals» (sheet 12), a society made up of equals in which any exercise of freedom that is not connected to public goals would be in vain[35].

Individuals must not use their freedom arbitrarily. On the contrary, they must use it for the common good – in other words, they must use it for ethical purposes[36].

Indeed, society and the state together represent a place which valorizes the individual – a place where a person’s intelligence is only improved through the community, with the firm belief that the individual will never evolve in his short lifetime, but only en masse and over the course of centuries. Thus, it is only in society that the citizen can rise up and attain fulfillment[37].

With these basic premises set forth at the outset, the middle pages of Introduzione delve into Private natural law, to which Romagnosi assigns a threefold role that he defines as «attributive», «directive» and «tutelary»[38], based on the actual needs of individuals[39].

A categorical imperative requires «that citizens be given what is due to them as per natural law»[40]: but times have changed, the community’s make-up has become more complex, and emerging groups have requested that new prerogatives be recognized. Under these circumstances, the sovereign power is thus tasked with defining the rights of all, and if necessary, changing the rights of individuals in the process. In any case, Romagnosi refuses to provide an abstract catalogue of individual rights[41].

Romagnosi’s detailed and well-founded analysis thus allowed him to develop an arsenal of arguments that could help him reformulate the meaning ofius naturae[42], which he would then use as a tool to explain the value of private law[43].

Although some rights are inalienable by nature – such as the right to freedom – the actual attribution of such rights can only take place if the statutory legislation provides for it.

It was no accident that Romagnosi repeatedly expressed this concept: «laws have a direct effect on the needs of each individual». All positive laws must be interpreted and understood in the light of the philosophical postulates that preceded them, while also taking the history of nations and the auxiliary branches of knowledge into consideration[44], as it is the constant integration of these factors that allows the legal scholar – be it a judge, lawyer or palatine – to fully grasp and express the ratio of said laws.

The importance of Introduzione allo studio del diritto is thus clear – it serves as the introduction to a discipline, but it is also a discipline to study in itself. It is both the starting point and the end goal of a university education that successfully comes full circle. Indeed, it is none other than a sittliche Staat that must be created: on paper, at least, it was the same Rechtsstaat (Constitutional state) that Romagnosi had always sought to describe.

Romagnosi revealed the moral depth that lies behind the doctrinal framework of his manuscript by reassessing how a person – as an individual in general, but even more so as a jurist – serves society.

It is certainly no easy task, and it cannot be completed by mechanistically carrying out formal, incumbent duties; on the contrary, it translates to any legal activity that ‘the moral man’ performs, from serving in public office to reaching private agreements with others[45].

Presented as such, the objective of positive law is to fulfill an ethical obligation that guarantees public happiness, to the benefit of all.

The inevitable classification of right and wrong is the great book that provides us with knowledge of the natural laws of reason. […]. The sum of these laws tells us which deeds must be put into practice and which must be avoided, and why […]. This is exactly what morality is[46].

3. Pure didactics or an ethical science?

So what was the goal of Romagnosi’s textbook? With ‘his’ legal encyclopedia, Romagnosi sought to refute any separation of the individual from the community, and he resolved to show the cupida legum iuventus not only what law was like in action, but also how it had been shaped over the centuries. This reference to the history of law was essential[47] to grasping the true needs of the nation and understanding the immanent reason underlying those needs[48]. Romagnosi’s aspirations would find their best expression in the program created by the Amministrazione centrale per le Facoltà legali (Central Administration for Departments of Legal Studies), which called for statutory provisions to be neither arbitrary nor mechanically reproduced from memory, but rather to be rooted in consciousness, thus becoming logical and moral conviction, which is the fundamental core of a jurist’s intellectual endowment.

For all these reasons, Romagnosi’s contribution cannot be ignored. While it may be true that the manuscript, like others of its ilk, provided an overview of all legal doctrines as well as the various parts of law to be studied, it is also true that the way it approached these themes was much more complex.

His work is noteworthy for its original structure: starting with the opening lines, it traced out a difficult path that the modern encyclopedia would have to complete from then onwards if it was to achieve its own independence as a science. That may be another story[49], but it is true that Romagnosi had something more in mind than a mechanistic presentation of the various legal disciplines when he thought of his encyclopedic endeavor. As clearly evidenced by the writings in his textbook, he theorized about a ‘science among sciences’ that rested on solid philosophical foundations, and that was built up methodically and organized on a historical basis, in order to provide students with an understanding of law in its entirety.

Thus, these unpublished pages provide a personal history of the author’s introductory course. The variety of registers displayed in the language Romagnosi used is only further testament to the link between methodology and philosophy, which he ably interweaved to lay the groundwork for the education of a new generation of jurists. In addition, he was also able to promote a vision of natural law as «science, law and the power to act in society»[50].

Romagnosi came to this subject matter late in life, having left behind the various forms of individualistic radicalism that had typified the revolutionary era; thus, he did not delve into it as much as other fields. Nevertheless, his ‘encyclopedia’ seems to be an appropriate way to summarize his life’s work.

________________________
[1] See S. Parini Vincenti, Ad auxilium vocatus, Studi sul «praticantato» da Napoleone alla Legge professionale del 1874: l’esperienza normativa, andStudi sul «praticantato» in età moderna. Romagnosi e la Scuola di eloquenza pratica legale (1808-1817), both inAvvocati e avvocatura nell’Italia dell’Ottocento, Bologna 2009, pp. 29-125 and pp. 127-199, particularly ntt. 24, 34, 39 (Appendice documentaria).

[2] This was an intense commitment on the part of Romagnosi. Having already been a professor at Parma and Pavia, he wanted to create a curriculum for aspiring law practitioners of law: his efforts to do so began with Progetto di Regolamento degli studi politico-legali, (in 198 artt.), written in 1807 but published with the incorrect date of 1803, together with Principi fondamentali di diritto amministrativo, aggiuntovi il Saggio filosofico sull’istruzione pubblica legale, which was never implemented by the government (Opere di G. D. Romagnosi, Milano, 1846, A. de Giorgi (ed.), VII, II, pp. 1189-1229 (hereafter referred to as EDG); and continued with Rapporto sul regolamento per gli studi pratici legali, which was based on two decrees, one issued on 15 November 1808 entitled Decreto riguardante il piano di istruzione generale (the original can be found in the State Archives of Milan (Archivio di Stato di Milano, hereafter referred to as ASMi), Collection Studi, m.p., folder 684) and the other on 15 April 1809 entitled simply Decreto ministeriale. These decrees established the three Special Postgraduate Schools of Alta Legislazione Civile e Criminale nei rapporti con l’amminstrazione pubblica (High Civil and Criminal Legislation as related to Public Administration, which was headed by Romagnosi), Diritto Pubblico e Commerciale (Public and Commercial Law, headed by Professor Franco Salfi), and Eloquenza Pratica Legale (Practical Legal Oratory, headed by Angelo Anelli).

[3] Fabio Luzzatto offered what he described in his own words as ‘the very first overview’ of the unpublished textbook (Introduzione enciclopedica allo studio del diritto nel di G. D. Romagnosi, in «Rivista di diritto privato», 5 (1935), nn. 3-4, pp. 189-216 and Id., Intorno ad un’opera inedita di Romagnosi in «Rivista internazionale di filosofia politica e sociale ‘Il Romagnosi’», 1 (1935), pp. 433-436). In a short piece, Luzzatto highlighted the «overwhelming endurance of [Romagnosi’s] principles and his unwillingness to give in or concede when it came to truths, no matter how unfavorable or difficult they may have been to the regime». Indeed, Luzzatto pointed out that while Romagnosi’s textbook may have only been a marginal part of his career – seeing as how the maestro was already widely acclaimed for many other, better-known works – it was nonetheless worth studying, as it attested to the moral strength and coherence of his ideological path at a crucial moment in his life.

[4] It is a well-known fact that Austrian police officers arrested Romagnosi on 26 May 1821 while he was giving Carlo Cattaneo a lesson. The charge brought against him was misprision of treason. It was only the beginning of an ordeal that would see him spend six terrible months in prison on the island of San Michele before he was eventually acquitted and released. Despite the acquittal, he was definitively banned from both public and private teaching, as he was considered an «individual who professes principles that are contrary to the education of youth» (F. Luzzatto, Gian Domenico Romagnosi. Il processo del 1821, extract from «Scuola Positiva. Rivista di diritto e procedura penale», n. s., 15 (1935), 7-8).

[5] We are far removed from the ‘eloquent jurists’ that were Romagnosi in his aureo Saggio and the much-lauded Girolamo Poggi (F. Colao, Avvocati del Risorgimento nella Toscana della Restaurazione, Bologna 2006, p.79, but even before in L. Mannori, Uno Stato per Romagnosi, II, La scoperta del Diritto Amministrativo, Milano 1987, p.18, nt. 29).

[6] Romagnosi meticulously reported to the general director of Public Education, Giuseppe Scopoli, on the status of the Scuole Speciali (Special Schools) and on the work carried out by the professors there, as shown in their frequent correspondence between November of 1814 and December of 1816. For this reason, we know that the lessons had already been moved to Brera by the end of 1814, due to Romagnosi’s own failing health (file 13340/5450 Del professore Romagnosi per la traslocazione in Brera del locale delle Scuole Speciali: Romagnosi to Scopoli, 15 December 1814); that the School of Public and Commercial Law had not been active since the Austrians arrived (Romagnosi to Scopoli, 9 February 1815); and that the curricula for the year 1816 were dedicated to an explanation of Regio Diritto (Royal Law) in the School of High Legislation and civile processura austriaca (Austrian criminal procedure) in the School of Practical Legal Oratory (Romagnosi to Scopoli , 15 September 1816). The year-end balance sheet for 1816 and the budget for 1817 – which Romagnosi was requested to provide with dispatch n. 3012 – attest to a general state of abandonment: «there is nothing left to do […] because everything has been reduced to the caretaker’s salary» (Romagnosi to Scopoli, 26 October 1816). Everything in ASMi, Fondo Studi, m.p., folder 181.

[7] For a detailed account of Progetto di Regolamento degli studi politico-legali see: G.D. Romagnosi. Lettere edite e inedite, collected and annotated by S. Fermi, with a preface by A. Solmi, Milano, 1935, n. 76, pp. 116-117; F. Gentile, Il progetto di Regolamento degli Studi Politico-Legali di G.D. Romagnosi, in L’Educazione Giuridica, II, Profili storici, Perugia, 1979, pp. 430-453; Mannori, Uno Stato per Romagnosi, II, [nt. 5], pp. 17-19; M. G. di Renzo Villata, Giandomenico Romagnosi e la pratica del diritto: riflessioni sparse during the academic conference entitled: Sapere accademico e pratica legale tra Antico Regime ed unificazione nazionale (XVIII-XX secolo), (Genova: 7-8 November 2008), V. Piergiovanni (ed.), Genova 2009, pp. 289-351. Printed version in EDG [nt.1], VII, II, pp. 1189-1229 and in Piatti’sOpere del professore G.D. Romagnosi, IV, Firenze 1832, pp. 267-318. See also, ASMi, Fondo Studi, m.p., folder 684.

[8] We can also find the following in Romagnosi’s Introduzione: «I will immerse you in the world in order to understand the true, complete and impassioned elements of the doctrine», sheet 16.

[9] For a general discussion of the issue: M. Meriggi, Aspetti dell’impiego di concetto in Lombardia (1816-1848); C. Mozzarelli, Il modello del pubblico funzionario nella Lombardia austriaca, both in L’educazione giuridica, IV, Il pubblico funzionario: modelli storico comparativi, II, Perugia 1981, pp. 331- 361 e pp. 439-459; M. G. di Renzo Villata, La formazione del giurista in Italia e l’influenza culturale europea tra Sette e Ottocento. Il caso della Lombardia, inFormare il Giurista esperienze nell’area lombarda tra Sette e Ottocento, Milano 2004, pp. 1-105; M. R. Di Simone, Percorsi del diritto tra Austria e Italia, secoli 17-20, Milano 2006, pp. 71-98; F. Rossi, Il cattivo funzionario. Fra responsabilità penale, amministrativa e disciplinare del Regno Lombardo-Veneto, Milano 2013.

[10] On this subject, see: M. Sarfatti Larson, The rise of professionalism: a sociological analysis, Berkeley, 1977; W. Tousijn, Tra Stato e mercato: le libere professioni in Italia in una prospettiva storico evolutiva, inLe libere professioni in Italia, Bologna, 1987, W. Tousijn (ed.), pp. 13-44; A. Ferraresi, Formazione professionale civile e militare tra Repubblica e Regno d’Italia. Il caso di Pavia, in La formazione del primo Stato italiano e Milano capitale 1802-1814, International Conference (Milano: 13-16 November 2002), Milano 2006, pp. 733-832, particularly pp. 795-796, and finally S. Parini Vincenti, Ad auxilium vocatus. [nt.1], pp. 62-74.

[11] L. Mannori, I ruoli dell’intellettuale nell’Italia napoleonica, in Istituzioni e cultura in eta` napoleonica, E. Brambilla, C. Capra, A. Scotti (ed.), Milano 2008, pp. 159-183, particularly pp. 160-162.

[12] Following the Napoleonic era, there was an initial and sudden transformation of the university system in 1816 (Sovrana Risoluzione 7 dicembre 1816, in ASMI, Studi m.p. folder 942). In accordance with the instructions issued in 1817 for the coming academic year, a new system was to be adopted that was the same as the one in place at the Empire’s other universities ( Istruzioni per l’attuazione degli studi dell’I. R. Università di Pavia, pel giorno 15 ottobre 1817, giusta le nuove prescrizioni di S.M.I.R.A ); however, the Regolamento generale (General regulations) would not be issued until 8 April 1825, and the restructuring process concluded in 1830 (for the relative texts, see Statuti e ordinamenti dell’Università di Pavia dal 1361 al 1859, Pavia 1925, pp. 325-330 and pp. 331-348; more details in M. G. di Renzo Villata,Tra Vienna, Milano e Pavia: un piano per un’università «dall’antico lustro assai decaduta» (1753-1773), inGli statuti universitari: tradizione dei testi e valenze politiche. Dall’originarietà degli Studi Generali all’autonomia delle Università (sec.XII-XXI), Messina, 14-17 aprile 2004, Bologna, 2007, pp. 507-546).

[13] There was a boom in didactic material offered by post-Napoleonic European countries that aimed to show their citizens – often in elementary terms – what their duties toward society and the state were: Doveri dei sudditi verso il loro monarca, Milano, I.R. stamperia, 1825, in Asmi, Presidenza di governo, folder 93, file 17- geheim, as previously cited in Rossi, Il cattivo funzionario [nt. 9], p. 54; R. Angeli, I doveri de’ cittadini verso la patria e degli impegati municipali etc… ad istruzione ed uso dei medesimi impegati, Roma 1824.

[14] More specifically, the Minister de Salvandy had already been pushing for its establishment since 1838, and the circular letter entitledCircolare 808 of 29 June 1840 (Moniteur 30 juin 1840) provided for the creation d’une chiare d’Encyclopédie à la Faculté de Droit de Paris, which was entrusted to De Barsac «pour objet de donner à l’étudiant qui débute une notion précise générale et élémentaire de la jurisprudence». Though it had changed in light of the experience in Germany, the introductory course in France for the L’École du Droit was nonetheless different than the course of Encyclopädie der Rechtswissenschaft: «La chaire récemment créée à Paris est une chaire d’encyclopédie et non de méthodologie […] en Allemagne le professeur est complètement libre dans son allure didaticque mais il ne peut être question de méthodologie en France où le matières à enseigner et l’ordre sont réglés par des lois» (P.L.A. Eschbach, De l’utilité d’un cours d’encyclopédie du droit, in Revue de la législation et de jurisprudence, XVI, juilett-décembre, (1842), pp. 257-263, particularly p. 260, n. 1. By the same author, see also Cours d’introduction générale a l’étude du droit, ou, Manuel d’encyclopédie juridique, Paris, 18462, in which we find the first citation (Avant-propos, V) and the complete transcription of the ministerial circular that appeared in the Moniteur). For a full exegesis of law studies in France, cfr. E. Lerminier, Introduction général à l’Histoire du droit, Bruxelles 1830, particularly Préface pp. XIV-XVI.

[15] The reference is to Entwurf einer juristischen Encyclopädie nebst etlichen Zugaben von der Politik, von Land- und Stadtgesetzen, von brauchbaren juristischen Büchern, published in Göttingen in 1757 and reprinted in the same city under the title Neuer Versuch einer Juristischen Encyclopädie und Methodologie in 1767 (although Hámza – infra – traces it to 1769, p. 150, nt. 50), in which Pütter (1725-1807) returned to themes that he had already discussed in his inaugural lecture for the year 1748 (Programma de necessaria in academiis tractanda rei iudiciariae imperiae scienciae, Göttingen 1748, as referred to by W. Ebel, Der Göttinger Professor Johann Stephan Pütter aus Iserlohn, Göttingen 1975, p. 62). The two editions presented new developments in the subject-matter: the first starts with a description of general concepts, followed by the correct way to arrange and treat the individual disciplines; the second (which is being referred to here) explains the purposes of those disciplines. For more on the subject, see: H. Monhaupt, Recht, Natur Geschichte als Argument, Quelle und Autorität in deutschen Rechtsenzyklopädien des 18. und frühen 19. Jahrhunderts, in Recht zwischen Natur und Geschichte, Symposion: 24-26 Nov. 1994, Frankfurt am Main 1997, pp. 73-102, particularly pp. 80-85; G. Valera, Dalla scienza generale alla enciclopedia: l’enciclopedia giuridica tedesca nella seconda metà del Settecento, in Enciclopedia e sapere scientifico. Il diritto e le scienze sociali nell’Enciclopedia giuridica italiana, A. Mazzacane, P. Schiera (ed.), Bologna 1990, p. 68, nt. 4 and pp. 70-71; G. Hámza, Comparative law and antiquity within the framework of legal humanism and natural law in Fundamina: A Journal of Legal History, XVI (2010), pp. 142-152, particularly pp. 149-151.

[16] Pütter, Neuer Versuch einer Juristischen Encyclopädie, p. 70, § 122. See Monhaupt, Recht, Natur Geschichte als Argument, [nt. 15], p. 82.

[17] This definition comes directly from Quintilian (Institutiones oratoriae libri XII, Milano 1997, lib. I, Cap. X, p. 118). On the other hand, a few examples of its use in textbooks can be found in: Eschbach, Manuel d’encyclopédie juridique, Avant-propos, II, nt.7 and De l’utilité d’un cours d’encyclopédie du droit [nt.14], 258, nt.7; but also in Den Tex, Encyclopaediae Jurisprudentiae, § 7., pp. 8-9 and Stöckhardt, Juristische Propaedeutik oder Vorschule der Rechtswissenschaft, Einleitung pp. 2-3, nt. 1.

[18] From Pütter onwards, the German territories would witness the publication of a series of textbooks that would only continue to strengthen this ‘encyclopedic’ debate. To cite but a few examples: A. F. Schott, Entwurf einer juristischen Encyclopädie und Methodologie, zum Gebrauch akademischer Vorlesungen, Leipzig 1772 (again in Monhaupt, Recht, Natur Geschichte als Argument, pp. 85-90 and Hámza, Comparative law and antiquity, pp. 151-152, cfr. for both [nt. 15]); J.F. Gildemeister, Juristische Encyclopädie und Methodologie, Duisburg 1783 (J. Schröder, Wissenschaftstheorie und Lehre der “praktischen Jurisprudenz” auf deutschen Universitäten an der Wende zum. 19 Jahrhundert, Frankfurt am Main 1979, pp. XX, 51-52, 112-113; Monhaupt, Recht, Natur Geschichte als Argument, p. 91); K. Sal. Zachariae, Grundlinien einer wissenschaftlichen juristischen Encyclopädi e, Leipzig 1795 (G. Valera, Profili giuridici della felicità, in C. Vetter (ed.) La felicità è un’idea nuova in Europa. Contributo al lessico della rivoluzione francese, I, Trieste 2005, pp. 80-100), and continuing up until Juristische Encyclopädie, auch zum Gebrauche bei akademischen Vorlesungen di N. N. Falck, Kiel 18252 (again in Monhaupt, Recht, Natur Geschichte als Argument, p. 101) and the pamphlet brevis sed ingeniosus according to Den Tex (supra, §14, p. 18) by G.F. Puchta, Encyclopädie als Einleitung zu Institutionen-Vorlesungen, Leipzig und Berlin 1825 (as referred to by W. Hastie, Outlines of the science of jurisprudence. An introduction to the systematic study of law, Edinburgh 1887, pp. 12-132).

[19] «in which the concept of an encyclopedia played an important role, and in which the Begriff der Rechtswissenschaft, sometimes mentioned in the title, was given prominence» » (G. Valera in Dalla scienza generale alla enciclopedia [nt. 15], pp 67-118).

[20] The encyclopedia was made into a European science in the wake of Leibniz’s Nova Methodus, which is unanimously considered the starting point for «le projets d’ouvrages synthétiques indispensables à le science du Droit», and the path can be traced as follows: in Belgium l’Encyclopédie du droit (Bruxelles 18432) by A. Roussel (1809-1875); in Holland l’Encyclopaediae Jurisprudentiae (Amstelodami 1839) by C. Anne den Tex (1795-1854), which among these works was the only one written in Latin, and in Russia, the Juristische Propaedeutik oder Vorschule der Rechtswissenschaft, zunächst für die Kaiserliche Rechtsschule zu St. Petersburg (Leipzig 18432) by H. R. Stöckhardt (1802-1848), which outlines a comparative framework based on the previous works. On the peculiar situation in Russia, cfr. also M. Silnizki, Geschichte des gelehrten Rechts in Russland: jurisprudencija an den Universitäten des Russischen Reiches 1700-1835, Frankfurt am Main 1997.

[21] August Böckh, who studied at Halle with Wolff, taught courses without interruption from 1809 to 1865 (26, to be precise). His ‘encyclopedic’ lessons tended to argue for a philosophical view of history that went beyond the mere ‘mimesis’ of events, so as to affirm the essential scientific contribution made by historical studies and their utility in numerous cultural contexts, not least of which the field of law. As valuable as his lessons were, they would only be published posthumously by his student E. Bratuscheck in 1877, in Leipzig, under the title Encyklopädie und Methodologie der philologischen Wissenschaften. The same types from 1866 were used for the republication of a second edition by R. Klussmann (ed.), while a partial translation was more recently carried out with La filologia come scienza storica: enciclopedia e metodologia delle scienze filologiche, A. Garzya (ed.), Napoli 1987. For an overview, cfr. V. Lau, Erzählen und Verstehen: historische Perspektiven der Hermeneutik, Würzburg 1999, § 4.2.2., pp. 395-399 and S. Caianiello, Scienza e tempo alle origini dello storicismo tedesco, Napoli 2005, pp. 238 and ss.

[22] News of the arrival of the successful textbook by A. von Hess – which in Italian was entitled Introduzione enciclopedico-metodologica allo studio politico-legale di A. de Hess (translated by G. Brambilla, Pavia 1820) – was disseminated by the Biblioteca italiana o sia Giornale di letteratura, scienza ed arti, XXI (1821), gennaio-marzo, p. 68, nt. 3. The work was meant for the universities and high schools of the German Hereditary Lands under the Austrian monarchy, and indeed it is of some importance for the subject at hand. It complied with the directives issued by Zeiller in 1808, as well as with the imperial education plan of 1810, and it reproduced the syllabus of the public course taught by Mr. Egger, Counselor of the Government and professor at Vienna. Cfr. S. Parini Vincenti, L’educazione del giurista: l’abbandono di un’arte per la conquista di una scienza, ovvero L’Introduzione enciclopedica alla Facoltà Politico Legale, in Formare il Giurista [nt. 9], pp. 365-401.

[23] The exact title of the course at the University of Pavia was Introduzione generale allo studio politico legale, diritto naturale e pubblico, diritto criminale (General introduction to political and legal studies, natural and public law, criminal law), whereas the textbooks that were being used – usually written by those who held the professorships of the courses themselves – separated the Introduzione enciclopedica allo studio politico-legale (Encyclopedic introduction to political and legal studies) from the other branches of study to be covered. For these other subjects, reference was made directly to the text by F. von Zeiller (Das Naturliche Privatrecht Vienna, 1808).

[24] S. Torre, L’«introduzione enciclopedica alle scienze giuridiche»: parabola di un insegnamento, in A. Mazzacane, C. Vano, (ed.), Università e professioni giuridiche in Europa nell’età liberale, Napoli 1994, pp. 151-192; P. Beneduce,L’ordine dell’esposizione. Introduzione alla giurisprudenza e regole dell’enciclopedismo in Italia nel secondo Ottocento, pp. 126-132 and F. Treggiari, Enciclopedia e ‘ricerca positiva’, both in Enciclopedia e sapere scientifico [nt. 15], pp. 119-161 and pp. 163-203.

[25] P. Cappellini, Systema iuris, Milano 1984, I, pp. 176 and ss.

[26] Introduzione enciclopedica allo studio del diritto, (hereafter referred to as Introduzione enciclopedica), Biblioteca A. May Bergamo, olim, Collection Beolchi, Romagnosi, Scritti varii, A, I, folders numbered 25 n. 6 and 25 n. 7, ora MMB 444, manuscript donated to the library by the Camozzi Vertova family in November 1899, with Romganosi’s lessons on civil law.

[27] Dating was determined by referring to the first Italian edition of Das Naturliche Privatrecht by Zeiller (Il diritto privato naturale, Milan 1818) as the earliest possible date (dies a quo), with the latest possible date (dies ad quem) being the end of Romagnosi’s public teaching career following the ban laid upon him in 1821 (F. Luzzatto, Gian Domenico Romagnosi. Il processo del 1821 [nt. 4]).

[28] See Luzzatto, Introduzione enciclopedica allo studio del diritto nel di G. D. Romagnosi [nt.3], pp. 190 and 216.

[29] Introduzione enciclopedica alla Studio del Diritto, sheet 7.

[30] «the law of nations, internal public law and civil law», Ibidem.

[31] «politics», which in turn is divided into diplomacy, internal public administration, fiscal policy and ecclesiastical law.

[32] Cited in Mannori, L’itinerario di un moderato. Libertà e pubblica opinione nel pensiero romagnosiano, [nt.7], p. 189.

[33] Introduzione enciclopedica alla Studio del Diritto, sheet 7.

[34] G. D. Romagnosi, Lettere a Giovanni Valeri sull’ordinamento della scienza della cosa pubblica, che servono da prolegomeni all’introduzione allo studio del diritto pubblico, in EDG, III, p. I, Oggetto proprio delle Genti e dei Governi tutti, Incivilimento, pp. 3-54, particularly p. 45.

[35] L. Lacchè, La nazione dei giuristi. Il canone eclettico, tra politica e cultura giuridica: spunti per una riflessione sull’esperienza italiana della Restaurazione, in Diritto, cultura giuridica e riforme nell’età di Maria Luigia, F. Micolo, G. Baggio, E. Fregoso (ed.), Parma 2011, pp. 263-307, particularly p. 284.

[36] «The exercise of a useful power in accordance with the rational and moral order» (G.D. Romagnosi, Assunto primo della scienza del diritto naturale, in EDG, III, parte I, pp. 553-686, particularly p. 604, XVII).

[37] The civilizing process is diachronic in nature, developing over generations and only within the realm of society. This is a clear reference to Introduzione allo studio del diritto pubblico universale (in EDG, III, p. I, pp. 57-491).

[38] Introduzione enciclopedica alla Studio del Diritto, sheets 7v and 8.

[39] Romagnosi discussed this theme in Perfezionamento politico-morale delle civili società. Articolo I, Osservazioni sui rapporti necessari di ordine del perfezionamento morale e politico delle nazioni in Id., Introduzione allo studio del diritto pubblico universale [nt.37], particularly §§ 427-429, pp. 475-480.

[40] Introduzione enciclopedica alla Studio del Diritto, sheet 8r.

[41] Assuming that the following is true: “It is the law that attributes certain fundamental rights to individuals, and it then establishes the rules for managing and safeguarding [said rights]» (Introduzione enciclopedica alla Studio del Diritto, sheet 8).

[42] Introduzione allo studio del diritto pubblico universale [nt.37], pp. 473-474, §§ 425-426.

[43] G.D. Romagnosi, Assunto primo della scienza del diritto naturale, [nt.36], particularly XVI, Della più vera e distinta nozione del Diritto naturale, pp. 600-601.

[44] Introduzione enciclopedica alla Studio del Diritto, sheet 7r.

[45] «With politics I mean the art of moving and directing the actions and interests of connected peoples […] as a mechanic distinguishes the straight line along which he wants a certain object to travel from an impulsive force, and from the way in which he controls that force. So the philosopher distinguishes the science of law from that of politics. The science of law perfectly resembles that straight line to travel; that of politics resembles the impulse to be applied» (Introduzione enciclopedica alla Studio del Diritto, sheet 7v).

[46] Introduzione enciclopedica alla Studio del Diritto, sheet 13r.

[47] His timeline divided the history of law into four fundamental periods, going from ancient China (551 B.C.) to the contemporary age (Introduzione enciclopedica alla Studio del Diritto, sheets 16 and ss.).

[48] Romagnosi went so far as to dedicate a paragraph to the need to “reconstruct the chain of history”: Della storia del diritti ed osservazioni critiche secondo lo Zeiller, Introduzione enciclopedica alla Studio del Diritto, sheet 17.

[49] As far as the encyclopedia as a discipline was concerned, the aporia that was its definition would remain unresolved in the years to follow, as it hovered somewhere between a merely ‘introductory’ subject and an actual science. Because of its proximity to subjects such as the history of law and philosophy, it was difficult to place within teaching programs. For more details see the works of Torre, Beneduce, Treggiari, and A. Fiori, Gli insegnamenti storico-giuridici alla Sapienza negli ultimi decenni del XIX secolo, in Historia et jus, 1(2013), paper 10. Full documentation of the life and work of Francesco Filomusi Guelfi in I. Birocchi, A. D’Angelis, Francesco Filomusi Guelfi enciclopedista convinto con considerazioni sull’inedita “Enciclopedia giuridica”, in M. Ascheri, G. Colli, P. Maffei (eds.), Manoscritti, editoria e biblioteche dal medioevo all’età contemporanea, Roma 2006, I, pp. 97-134 and I. Birocchi, F. Filomusi Guelfi, in Dizionario Biografico dei Giuristi Italiani, Bologna 2013, I, pp. 863-865.

[50] Progetto di Regolamento (Section II, art. 41), [nt.2] particularly p. 1198. For more details see also Introduzione enciclopedica, sheet 12.

The Flogging Machine. Romagnosi in Search of the Perfect Punishment

Loredana Garlati

Università degli studi di Milano-Bicocca

loredana.garlati@unimib.it

Abstract: In 1806 Luosi submitted its draft penal code to Romagnosi, which wrote a new draft code, the Progetto sostituito, and wrote the Motivi. In this essay I’ll examine an instrument ingenious and terrible, the flogging machine, and the philosophy of punishment that prevailed in the first decade of the nineteenth century in Italy. In that period the achievements of the Enlightenment mingled with emerging repressive maneuvers.

Keywords: Romagnosi, Gian Domenico; Progetto sostituito; Criminal law; Flogging machine; Penalties

Table of contents: 1. Utilitarianism, proportionality and repressive effectiveness of the punishment.2. “False pretenses of humanity”: rethinking capital punishment.3. The flogging machine from juridical engineering to penal economy.

1. Utilitarianism, proportionality and repressive effectiveness of the punishment. – Gian Domenico Romagnosi, major protagonist in 17th-18 th century legal culture, is particularly identified with the 1807 Code of Criminal Procedure. It was the only ‘national’ code to be adopted in the years when Napoleonic Imperialism was imposed on Italy with weapons and laws. He was the expression of that fertile Po Valley breeding ground, which in the second half of the 18th century onwards directed men and ideas to set up new Italian criminal laws: the fervor of Verri and Beccaria had left worthy heirs, who between 1790 and 1810 were active in conciliating the great tradition of the past with the new instances of the present.

Many of the laws written in those years, which were very different from each other in content and political inspiration, bear the authoritative imprint of their author: it is what happened with the Progetto sostituito of the penal code written by Romagnosi in 1806, a document, as Friedman states that is not entirely unknown to scholars of criminal law history[1]. However, still today it has not been fully analyzed[2], which is the reason why in this short essay we will delineate a few considerations on the topic of exacerbation of penal sanctions, since, as expressed by Romagnosi in his Motivi that accompanies the Progetto sostituito[3], it is the sanctions, intended as the truly operational part of the code, that determine the positive or negative outcome of a penal law[4].

It is difficult to explain the Romagnosian conception of punishment in a few words: he partly takes refuge in what Pessina defined as the absurd hypothesis of the social contract[5] of the Beccarian school[6]

sostituendovi la dottrina che lo stato sociale è il vero stato di natura dell’uomo come quello ch’è fondato nella necessità di fatto della natura umana (substituting the doctrine that the welfare state is the true natural state of man, like that which is founded on the basic needs of human nature)[7]

and generates a theorization in which opposing forces merged and were reconciled, such as the general-preventive goal to be achieved through exemplarity, respecting utilitarian criteria and efficacy and the rigorous observance of principles of proportionalism and retribution[8].

Far from any humanitarianism, Romagnosi writes that in order to achieve such results, the punishments must be characterized by certainty and rigor and that prevention leads to

trattare il colpevole (che è sempre un essere umano) come un mezzo per un fine – l’esempio dato agli altri, l’intimidazione a scopi di difesa sociale e di lotta alla criminalità – che è a lui estraneo ed è proprio della società intesa come ente collettivo (treating the offender (who is still a human being) as a means to an end – the example given to others, using intimidation as a social defense mechanism and for fighting crime – which is alien to him, with society understood as a collective entity)[9].

At the same time, the search for an appropriate proportionalist ideology allows to mitigate the negative consequences inherent in the acceptance of the idea of exemplary punishment, which often risks, if used for responding to the mere objective of prevention, to appear excessive respect to the seriousness of the offense.

However, it is the utilitarian inspiration which our author believes is victorious, through the establishment of a quantitative relationship between crime and punishment, well expressed by terminology borrowed from the vocabulary of arithmetic.

If from Beccaria on, the intent of the ‘modern’ penal lawyer was to maintain the difficult balance between protection of civil liberties and statism, compensating social defense with the protection of individual rights (and thus balancing contractualism with utilitarianism), Romagnosi breaks this symmetry suppressing

uno dei due termini dell’equazione e ponendo l’accento esclusivamente sull’esigenza della difesa sociale, con risultati potenzialmente inaccettabili per chi professa una visione liberale e garantistica del diritto penale (one of the two terms of the equation, and exclusively focusing on the need for social defense, with potentially unacceptable results for those who profess a liberal and protective view of civil liberties in penal law)[10].

The theoretical substrate of the composite is the raw material with which the author shapes his belief: for Romagnosi only the punishments giving the impression of physical pain were effective, and therefore useful, in the belief that man is able to become accustomed to anything (hard work, lack of food, and loss of freedom), but the prospect of real, acute, periodic and repeated suffering will always be unbearable.

This is what emerges from Genesi del diritto penale, the work of a lifetime, which was first published in 1791, but as is well known, it took Romagnosi other thirty-two years to complete it[11]. And it is also what emerges from the analysis of the Progetto sostituito. It is the first significant element: it reveals, in fact, close consistency between the speculative Romagnosi and the Romagnosi legislator. Not only. It is undeniable that he saw an opportunity in the occasion offered to him by Luosi to render his philosophy of law patrimony into normative precepts, which in light of the experience he had acquired in the editing of his’ penal code[12], made the draft a training ground for experimentation of the doctrinal construction[13].

The topic of exacerbation of punishment, while representing only a fragment of the entire picture on regulations, is still able to offer significant insights.

It is necessary to make a first consideration: stiffer penalties responded perfectly to the values preached by the mature enlightenment. The doctrinal and legislative works of the time show that humanitarianism with which we usually consider the vision of penal law of the philosophes, in reality only leave a mark on a period or, rather, involve only some of its exponents. In fact, there is another side, equally significant, that fully adheres to the rigid rationalism of punishment and which re-presents it from a conservative viewpoint, fitting in with the general climate of regression which affects society, institutions, and legal policy. Adherence to this second consideration reaches its zenith in the years of frantic transition from the old to the new system, when that exasperated esprit de géométrie is recovered from the penal justice system during the enlightenment, functional to the new repressive demands, with disconcerting results at times.

It is what happened with Romagnosi: Romagnosi liked little or nothing about the correction (penal) building erected by Luosi. He criticized the lack of effectiveness, as well as the absence of any possibility for the ranking and proportionality of the sanctions. At the basis of the system, Romagnosi sustained, a sentence of absolute value was necessary, which could serve as the foundation for the evaluation of all the others, with which to exacerbate, increase, combine, or transform the punishment to fit the multitude of practical cases[14]. The words of Luosi, instead, were limited to finding the sanctions in traditional apparatus, aimed at affecting freedom, substance or honor, more often ineffective and therefore useless:

per chi non ha sostanze la classe della pena pecuniaria è nulla; e il numero maggior dei delinquenti è fra quelli che non posseggono nulla. Per chi non conosce il sentimento della riputazione o si è avvezzato a sprezzarlo, l’infamia di fatto è nulla: e la riputazione non ha luogo che fra gente onesta. La perdita della libertà per chi trae una vita dura ed uniforme o è nulla, o presto diviene nulla e non colpisce la fantasia degli spettatori come convien ad una pena. Rimangono le fatiche corporali e i dolori fisici positivi. Le prime non affettano quasi mai con quel terrore che fa d’uopo alla punizione. I secondi poi (a riserva della morte) è d’uopo ottemperarli in maniera che nel mentre in cui possano incuter timore e servir di correzione non attentino all’esistenza e non lascino rotture corporali permanenti onde ridurre un uomo nell’impotenza di usare in appresso delle sue membra (for those without property, the class of the pecuniary punishment means nothing; and the greatest number of offenders is among those who possess nothing. For those unfamiliar with the sentiment of reputation or are accustomed to scorning it, infamy is in fact nothing: reputation has no place except among honest people. The loss of liberty for those who lead a hard and flat life is either null or will soon become null and does not capture the imagination of the audience as a punishment behooves. Bodily fatigue and positive physical pain remain. The first one almost never instills the terror that is necessary in a punishment. The latter (subject to death) is then necessary so that they can infuse terror and serve as a form of correction. It does not make an attempt on his life, nor leave permanent physical damage that would leave a man without the power to use his limbs afterwards)[15].

It was therefore necessary to devise something that would serve as a perpetual supplement, which was corrective to the imperfections present in any kind of punishment. But such a remedy, according to Romagnosi, already existed and it was flogging, to be applied with a special machine he had designed[16], capable of transforming the “engineering of penal law” of the author into engineering tout court[17].

In these pages we will deal exclusively with the discipline of flagellation designed for punishments of criminal sentences, divided into major and minor criminal penalties[18] (for which sentences of the local police came after), a classification coordinated by the jurisdiction of the different courts[19].

The punishments for the worst crimes corresponded, in Luosi’s version, to the sentences for serious felonies[20]: there were eight in both normative texts, and notwithstanding the different classificatory labels, they totally overlapped. The lists began with the death penalty, moving on to shackles, penitentiary, prison, the pillory, the posting of the notice, permanent disqualification from holding public office or from the exercise of an art or trade, ending with exile[21]. The first four were major and not cumulative; the last four were accessory and used for increasing the basic sanction[22].

Even death, which in the legislative proposal of Luosi would seem aseptically imparted by beheading[23], in reality, forms of exacerbation were found as an exception in order to satisfy proportionalist-remunerative demands.

2. “False pretenses of humanity”: rethinking capital punishment. – The Luosi draft, in fact, ‘limited’ itself to asking for a more impressive apparatus for the execution of the death penalty (the so-called morte specialmente esemplare) in the case of particularly serious crimes, the determination of which was strictly left to the law. Once a beheading took place, the head was hoisted up on a pole with a sign indicating the name and country of the offender, title and aggravating quality of the crime: the macabre trophy was displayed for an entire day[24].

On this point, in fact, Luosi contradicted his previous draft of 1801[25], which in part was modeled on the lines of those in the arsenal of sanctions[26], however varying the punitive strategy.

In the 1801 draft, death did not experience any exacerbation or ex post[27] theatricality. The afterthought, a few years later, can perhaps be attributed to a political and ideological change: after the revolutionary code[28] and following the end of the Terror experience, Benthamite utilitarian-style philosophies began to take root in France, sending the principles expressed by Beccaria[29] to the background and almost to eliminating any memory of them. Anthropological pessimism spread skepticism on the possibility of entrusting the objective of social rehabilitation of the offender to the sentence.

Il diritto penale è quindi riscoperto e rivalutato unicamente nelle sue potenzialità terroristiche dissuasive, cioè quale argine al dilagare dei delitti e come strumento atto a presidiare la pubblica sicurezza e le istituzioni politiche costituite. In tal modo ritorna in auge la teorica dell’esemplarità della pena (di cui Bentham è appunto uno dei moderni profeti) (Penal law was therefore only rediscovered and re-evaluated as a potential terrorist deterrent, ie as a barrier to the spread of crime and as a tool for protecting public security and the established political institutions. In this way, the theoretical exemplary sentence came back into vogue (for which Bentham is one of the modern prophets.)[30]

Already the draft of the Code criminel elaborated in France in 1801, which inspired the future Code of 1810[31], contemplated a gruesome scenographic framework accompanying the extreme sentence, reserved for those who had committed the most heinous crimes, such as parricide, uxoricide, murder, arson, poisoning and sadism. In this kind of theatre pièce next to the red tunic of revolutionary memory, not missing was the public display of the convicted person for an hour, the placard of infamy, the amputation of his right hand before the death sentence itself[32]: a choreography in part maintained in the final 1810 version[33].

A further step came with the Act of 25 February 1804[34]: despite having achieved a modest objective compared to the original ambitious program of the unification of criminal law, this measure assumed great political and legal importance, showing how

«tra il legislatore repubblicano e i principi umanitari dell’illuminismo penale si fosse scavato un solco incolmabile» («between the Republican legislator and the humanitarian principles of penal enlightenment an impassable chasm had been dug»)[35].

The law aimed to bring back repressive characteristics and ferocious intimidation to punishment, combined with the fulfillment of the demand for proportionality and exemplarity. If Luosi did not fail to criticize it at first, he instead seemed to follow certain postulates in his draft in 1806, in line with the main issues of criminal policy that were unraveling in France. It could not be otherwise, given the institutional and administrative interdependence between the two territorial realities, on one side and on the other of the Alps.

The comments accompanying the Luosi draft of 1806 show some regret for having again included death among the sentences:

ai piedi dell’altare della Giustizia […] dovemmo fare il duro sacrificio de’ liberali nostri principi, e impor silenzio ai voti del nostro cuore, allorché convinti da una fatale esperienza con linee di sangue vergammo noi pure fra le pene quella di morte (at the foot of the altar of Justice […] we had to make the hard sacrifice with ‘our liberal principles, and impose silence to the votes of our heart, when convinced by a fatal experience, with lines of blood we also wrote the death sentence among the others)[36].

He returns however, to impose a healthy and lucid realism that still gives space, albeit limited, to the ‘mournful’ remedy:

la fredda ragione ha soggiogato il sentimento. Ella colla verità di sua luce impedì ai nostri sguardi d’essere abbarbagliati da quei falsi lampi d’umanità, di filosofia, d’eloquenza che scintillarono sull’orizzonte di Europa nel secolo diciottesimo e strapparono al consenso di alcuni celebri e grandi Regnanti l’abolizione della pena di morte (cold reasoning has subdued feeling. With the truth of its light it prevented us from being dazzled by those false pretenses of humanity, philosophy and eloquence that glowed on the horizon of Europe in the 18th century and obtained consent for the abolition of the death penalty by several renowned and great Rulers)[37].

Romagnosi used harsher tones, introducing the distinction between simple and qualified death, but did not indicate the concrete ways of enforcing it in the Progetto sostituito[38]. However, it is inevitable that in the crimes in which the offender goes beyond the sentiments of natural instincts and good behaviour, or where an excess of evil passion is found, which can bring horror and indignation to the social collectivity, the legislature cannot, according to the Parmanese jurist, settle for an ordinary form of death. A punishment which is identical in the way it is enforced would induce the multitudes to equate the crimes of different types and to give the same reprehension to the murder of a villain as to that of a prince or equalize the killing of an outsider to that of one’s own parents[39] .

According to Romagnosi, therefore, even death should instill terror in its application, but in a different way than what was prepared by the European legislation of that time, which was not very able to fulfill that goal. The theatricality foreseen by the revolutionary code of 1791 did not seem appropriate: the red robes imposed on the murderers, the arsonists and the poisoners, the black veils with which they covered the face of the parricide[40], or the various symbolisms are more « propri a far ridere che a recar spavento (fit to make people laugh than to make them afraid)»[41].

Article 5 of the Law of February 25, 1804, reproduced in the Luosi draft, showed instead according to Romagnosi, obvious confusion between the purpose of the publicity of the sentence and the reason that had induced the legislature to choose the fixing of the truncated head of the offender on a pole as exemplary death[42]. Therefore, a punishment capable of generating fear which was proportionate to the gravity of the crime was lacking[43], since the penalty is sought to be terrible in order to adequately fulfill its objective, which is to correct the offender (objective which Romagnosi does not believe in), but to prevent, in an intimidating prospect, the future commission of crimes. It is appropriate that the legislator is guided by sole necessity and utility (the two terms being constantly referred to), avoiding certain manners or not giving in to the lure of some sirens[44].

Bisogna anche guardarsi da una certa zerbineria legislativa che con un’aria plausibile ci trascina a far l’apoteosi d’una femminile ritrosia nell’irrogare i supplizi […]. Ci vuol violenza, è vero, a dettar certe pene a sangue freddo, ma bisogna vincersi. Bisogna anche affrontare la pretesa umanità del secolo e dichiarare che il fine della punizione è quello di incutere terrore (It is important to look out for a certain legislative gallantry which with a plausible air leads us to make the apotheosis of a feminine reluctance in imposing the punishments […]. It takes violence, it is true, to order certain punishments in cold blood, but this has to be accepted. We must also address the alleged humanity of the century and declare that the purpose of punishment is to instill terror[45].

These arguments reappeared in the 1809 draft, entrusted to a commission of jurists, among which the name of Romagnosi stands out. After the failure to proclaim the treatise of 1806, work in the field of criminality resumed and three years after the Progetto sostituito, exemplarity and severity of the punishment became the trade-mark of the newly proposed legislation: an already tried terrorist apparatus not far from the transalpine legislation which was due to enter into force in 1811 and for which the Italian ruling class shared the centralist framework[46], and at the same time was in line with the continuity of the Romagnosian ideology.

3. The flogging machine from juridical engineering to penal economy. – In a society beset by the increase of crime and obsessed by the need to maintain public order, penal law is perceived as a ‘military’ defense of power, and not as a pedagogical tool.

Exemplarity is the watchword that can guarantee punishments aimed at achieving control of the society, or a cold social hygienism[47]. More than the crime-punishment relationship, it is necessary to look at the offender-punishment relationship, based on a kind of psychic determinism: the sentence must win over the criminal tendency with its psychological pressure. If the sentences must instill fear, not as a result of the wickedness of the legislator-man, but as a cold calculation of need, then Romagnosi contrived the most bizarre punishment to do this, and at the same time was more cynically utilitarian than it is possible to imagine: the flogging machine.

This would seem to be a step backwards compared to what was asserted by members of the insurgents of jurists against flogging in Lombardia. It had an Austrian matrix, present in the Josephine Code of 1787[48] and later with the development of the Code of 1803[49], and was considered shameful for a population of superior refinement and culture such as the Lombardy one.

In reality, the floggings were a remedy which were hated more in form than in substance, as confirmed by a number of previous projects completed in the Milanese area: the generalized contempt for this form of hardening of the sentence clashed with the need to scale the punishment not only in regard to the type of offense, but also to the social background of the offender, in clear opposition to the principle of equality of the legal subject who was the recipient of the law[50].

First Beccaria[51], Luigi Villa[52] and Peter Mantegazza[53] who had not spread an inflamed announcement, but had used caution: it was necessary to restrict the use of the floggings to the lowest social classes (not having the honor that such a punishment risked offending), or, on the contrary, to extend the provision to all, but avoiding its enforcement in public in order to spare the person from consequent infamy.

Romagnosi, therefore, seemed to fit into the heart of Italian culture (Lombardia in particular), where tensions resumed and were taken to extreme consequences.

The proposed proportionalist model of enlightenment, in an attempt to objectify the criminal proceedings, structured the relationship between crime and punishment on formal logic criteria. The cases were classified according to a scale of severity of the values, which would have had to correspond to the sentences according to applicative automatisms that were extremely simplified and impersonal. This scheme, however, was not enough to ensure compliance with the principle of proportionality, which descended from the general to the particular, to create an almost tailor-made sentence for each person, rather than entire criminal categories. If the idea of proportion is therefore the foundation around which the punitive system hinges, flogging, for Romagnosi, is the unit of measure.

The Progetto sostituito does not provide us with much useful information on the system of flogging. Here we find only cold and impersonal regulations. Article 115, in fact, limits itself to pointing out that flagellation may be used only as a supplement or exacerbation[54], with the sole exception for the local police punishments, which could increase to the rank of principal sentence in cases established by law[55], and did not ever constitute exacerbation of the death penalty[56].

Title VIII, devoted entirely to the subject, was composed of ten intricate provisions describing the implementation of the flogging. It could take place only in cases expressly provided by law, with regard to both men and women in life sentences, in penitentiaries, houses of correction or fortresses, in the presence of the prison ‘population’. When it constituted an increase in the sentence of shackling or in penitentiaries, for the first time it was executed in front of the entire community, except in the case of women or children under the age of twenty[57].

The last four long and complicated rules governing how the number of strokes were to be imposed in minute detail, as determined in practice by the courts from a minimum and a maximum set by the law, which also indicated the times of recurrence of the punishment. The calculation was extremely complex, and this is not the place to go into detail: it is sufficient to recall that the absolute maximum limit of possible lashings to be imposed in a single session was sixty and the minimum was six, to be repeated even once a week[58].

The real source of knowledge of Romagnosi’s thinking was Motivi, which revealed a dark side of penal thought by an author who was often celebrated as the founder of modern and liberal criminal law. Proceeding by degrees, first with logical arguments and then juridical ones, according to a dialectical pro and contra scheme, the Emilian lawyer was first committed to demonstrating the falsity of certain critical statements against such a form of exacerbation, to then launch into a passionate defense of flogging, by proving both the need and the opportunity.

Si è proclamata la dolcezza delle pene e si è declamato contro la loro severità. Ma dolcezza e severità sono due parole relative le quali non determinano nulla di preciso, non danno niuna direzione particolare; non esimono regola alcuna, non operano nulla, non dicono nulla. Il legislatore non conosce veramente che necessità e moderazione. La necessità viene determinata dalla ragione della pubblica sicurezza cui deve difendere dai danni dei facinoroso. La moderazione è lo spirito col quale egli non eccede i confini di questa necessità. La dolcezza degenera in debolezza allorché il freno contro il delitto non è abbastanza efficace a spegnere le cagioni. La severità degenera in tirannia allorché si tormenta al di là del bisogno della completa sicurezza (He proclaimed the mildness of the sentences and ranted against their severity. But mildness and severity are two related words that do not determine anything specific, nor give any particular direction, nor express any law, nor serve anything or say anything. The legislator knows nothing but necessity and moderation. The need is determined by reason of public security which must be defended from the damage of the ruffians. Moderation is the spirit in which one does not go beyond the boundaries of this need. Mildness degenerates into weakness when the deterrent against crime is not effective enough to extinguish the causes. A heavy hand degenerates into tyranny when it torments beyond the need of complete safety[59].

Therefore

farebbe d’uopo d’una tale pena che lasciasse una memoria salutare nella correzione, in vece di lasciare il confuso sentimento d’una privazion che svanisce troppo presto; e non agisce acutamente su la memoria di chi la provò, e su la fantasia di chi ne fu spettatore (such a punishment is needed that leaves a healthy memory in the correction, instead of leaving a confused feeling of privation that vanishes too soon and does not act acutely on the memory of those who experienced it, and the imagination of those who were spectators)[60].

Starting from these premises, Romagnosi believed that any criticism of flogging responded more to common approaches than to any real negative effects regarding it, with the result that a judgment which was legally impartial and neutral hid a misguided sense of ethics and morality[61].

The author invites those who criticize such a solution, considering it barbaric and uncivil, to reflect on the commonly accepted opinion that the floggings are an excellent remedy for those individuals, such as street thugs, for whom traditional penalties are ineffective. Neither a fine nor imprisonment are an effective punitive response to offenders who usually are without property or are poor, ready to see prison not as an affliction but as a delight; exile would be excessive and suspension from a trade for those who do not have one would be impractical. All that can be done is to beat the thief with twelve or fifteen well-aimed lashes to quell any foolish ambition or criminal passion[62]. The echo of Kaunitz resonates here in a report from 17 May 1780, complaining about the action by the Senate for the ordinary sentences of boys who were lazy or addicted to petty theft, for which the chancellor suggested instead to adopt a summary and cursory procedure, in imitation of what was happening in Vienna: once captured, they had to be beaten, for one day or more[63].

Romagnosi also recalled that the beatings were a common tool of domestic discipline. In likening the sovereign or the government to the good father of a family, it would hence allow it to also imitate those private punishments[64].

The real motives for the support of flagellation are found in the reasoning of penal economy, which imposes the use of everything that could be helpful to achieve the goal. If the Penal Code is not a statute of chivalry, as noted by the jurist from Salsomaggiore, the law of necessity must follow[65], which requires the legislator to render the goal of prevention into legal precepts, including general and special penalties[66], identified on the basis of scalability to allow for a proportional adjustment to the crimes[67]: it is the speculation of Genesi translated into practice.

Here, then, the flogging machine, simple and frightening at the same time, consists of a large wooden base « come quella che serve alle ruote colle quali si fa la corda (like that which serves the wheels to make cord with)»[68], on which other boards are erected perpendicular to it, crossed by a twisted wood that moves by rotation. At one end of this wooden cross hangs a large iron rod that is used to turn the wood.

Of the wooden cross in object a hole is made at a certain distance from the opposite end of the highest part

Pel ricordato legno trasversale si pratichi ad una certa distanza dall’estremità opposta a quella da cui pende il vette un foro» per inserirvi una corda di ferro e un bastone, munito di un globo mobile di piombo di vario peso

in modo che si possa levare a piacere. Il bastone sorta fuori dal globo, e all’estremità del medesimo pendono verghe di sanguine o di cornio, fissate in guisa da mutarle ad ogni opportunità (insert an iron cord and a stick, fitted with a movable lead ball of various weights so that it can be changed at will. The stick rises from the ball, and at the end of it dogwood or cornel rods, fixed in such a way that they could easily be changed)[69].

The description is accompanied by detailed calculations and measurements[70], which if adhered to allow the machine to act not as a means to inflict pain freely, but as a dispenser of fair and impartial punishment. The condemned man lies with bare shoulders at a distance sufficient enough to allow the ends of the rods to hit his entire back. From the part of the plank the lever is lifted a little more than a quarter of a circle and is set free, in order to move the rods, which will rise and lower with momentum that is proportional to the weight of the offender and that of the globe, striking blows with the force and the strength that is opportune to wield. This result is obtained by changing the weight of the movable ball placed at the end of the rod[71].

The flogging machine, therefore, allows to mitigate the abstract equality of the sentences, which do not consider the impact of personal reflections and the dissimilar social harm procured by the execution of the punishments in the hands of anyone different from them for sex, age, education, but especially for their perception of their sense of honour[72]. The necessary relativism inherent in the nature of things cannot answer with the uniformity of the law, in order to not risk creating a penal law which is unfair, improvident and defective, even if it theoretically meets the principles of equity[73].

There is no shortage of information on how to fulfill and comply with the proportionalist principle in order to avoid monstrous aberrations. Thus, the punishment by flogging must be inversely proportional to the time of the principal penalty.

It should, however, also take into account the specific physical constitution of the condemned: so that each time that the flogging is imposed with a greater number of blows, a longer interval is established between the successive ones, in order to allow a complete recovery[74].

In accordance with the principle of proportionality, Romagnosi followed a generally accepted rule, i.e. the shorter the sentence time, the stronger, though more infrequent, must be the floggings

perché nella memoria più forti rimangono le rimembranze dolorose non in proporzione della ripetizione, ma in proporzion della forza delle impressioni ricevute nell’atto della sensazione. Ora nella condanna di tempo minore più presto procurandosi la libertà del delinquente era d’uopo di preparare nell’anima di lui una più viva memoria salutare di castigo valevole a frenarlo dal ricadere nel delitto allorché fosse in libertà (because in the strongest memories the painful memories remain not in proportion to the repetition, but in proportion to the strength of the impressions received in the action of the sensations. Now in shorter sentences, in procuring the freedom of the criminal sooner it was necessary to prepare a strong memory of punishment in his soul, in order to stop him from committing crime when released)[75].

Each time that the flogging is prepared with the highest possible number of blows, it is expected to take place in the prison in the presence of all prisoners who have not been condemned to receive the same punishment:

ivi essendovi altri condannati che non furono assoggettati a così fatta pena, era d’uopo che allo spettacolo del dolore del paziente si avvezzassero ad associare l’idea del maggior dolore all’idea del delitto maggiore di quello ch’essi commisero (since there were other prisoners not subject to such a punishment, it was necessary that the exhibition of the victim’s suffering would make them associate the idea of more intense suffering to the idea of a more severe crime than the one which they themselves had committed)[76].

In as much as this practice was reserved for the most heinous crimes, it was therefore very rare. Thus, inurement to the spectacle of suffering was avoided and the goal of leaving a strong impression on the soul of the spectator was reached.

Collo stabilire per tanto le sole pene comuni, altro non si fa che tessere la prima orditura della ragion criminale. Il compimento sta nella pena supplementare di un valor certo e tale che si possa dividere in tutte le frazioni necessarie a pareggiare l’efficacia della pena. Avvi altre pene, fuorché quella che io ho suggerito, che soddisfaccia a questa mira? (With the establishment therefore of only the common sentences, it does nothing else but weave the first array of criminal reason. The fulfillment lies in the additional punishment of a certain value, which we can divide into all the fractions that are necessary to equalize the effectiveness of the punishment. Are there other punishments, outside what I have suggested, that satisfy this purpose?)[77]


“È una macchina curiosa” disse l’ufficiale all’esploratore, abbracciando con uno sguardo in certo senso ammirato la macchina, che pur conosceva bene (“It ‘a curious machine,” said the officer to the explorer, embracing with a look, in some way admiring the machine, that he nonetheless knew well).

A machine consisting of a bed, boards, wheels and a glass harrow with needles embedded in it, was used to inscribe the name of the law violated on the body of the condemned. Everyone, through the window, could see how the inscription was written on the body: a long needle wrote and a short one sprayed water to wash away the blood and thus keep the writing clear. The needles embroidered the man’s back, deeper and deeper: it took six hours before the prisoner lost consciousness, twelve to die, and the sentence was finally executed.

Kafka, about a century after Romagnosi, in his short story “In the Penal Colony”[78], for one of those curious and perhaps inexplicable coincidences, blends fiction and reality. Its pages of hallucinated normality are most likely worthy for showing us how sometimes what appears as a choice that is rationally needed in the spasmodic search of the perfect punishment, can transform into a nightmare of horror through the intervention of a morbid human inclination.

We must perhaps give credit to artistic transfiguration to guess what the fate of the machine devised by Romagnosi would have been if it had been really used? The intuition of the literary genius helps us to reflect on the potentially devastating outcomes inherent in blind adherence to the canons of geometric rationalism of enlightenment memory.

________________________
[1] G. S. Tempia, Il progetto di codice penale di G.D. Romagnosi, in «Rassegna Nazionale», 20, 4 (1884), pp. 611-620; F. Luzzatto, Giandomenico Romagnosi. Suo soggiorno a Milano e sua collaborazione al Progetto di codice penale del Regno Italico (1806-1814), in «La Scuola Positiva», n.s. XV, 1 (1935), pp. 393-412; M. Roberti,Milano capitale napoleonica. La formazione di uno Stato moderno. 1796-1814, vol. II, Milano 1947, p. 81; E. Dezza,Il codice di procedura penale del Regno italico (1807). Storia di un decennio di elaborazione legislativa, Padova 1983, pp. 247-255; Id., Appunti sulla codificazione penale nel primo Regno d’Italia: il progetto del 1809, in Id., Saggi di storia del diritto penale moderno, Milano 1992, p. 236; A. Cadoppi, L’albero genealogico dei codici penali italiani. Spunti di riflessione dal codice penale del Canton Ticino del 1816, in Codice penale della Repubblica e Cantone del Ticino (1816) S. Vinciguerra (ed.), Padova 2006, p. CLXXV, E. Dezza, Multa renascentur quae iam cecidere. La plurisecolare vicenda del Progetto sostituito di Giandomenico Romagnosi, in Criminalia, 2009, pp. 157-187.

[2] R. Isotton, Il Progetto sostituito di codice penale per il Regno d’Italia di G.D. Romagnosi (1806). Prima trascrizione, in «Diritto penale XXI secolo», anno V, 1 (2006), p. 120. For the origin and structure of this project see pp. 119-130.

[3] The two part manuscript is preserved at the Biblioteca Nazionale Centrale of Florence (Fondo Nazionale 1806, II, IV, 189). The first part is the Progetto Sostituito, parte prima. Disposizioni Generali, tit. I-XII with 240 articles [from now on, Progetto sostituito]. The second part is the Motivi delle Note marginali e del Progetto Sostituito [from now on, Motivi ]. The transcription of the Progetto by R. Isotton is used in this essay, (nt. 2), pp. 131-177. The Motivi, instead, has not been transcribed yet.

[4] Motivi (nt. 3), Appendice al titolo delle pene, All’articolo XLII, Sezione Prima § 1, f. 26.

[5] E. Pessina, Letteratura del diritto criminale, in P. Rossi, Trattato di diritto penale, Torino 1859, p. 566.

[6] On common and contrast points between Romagnosi and Beccaria see R. Ghiringhelli, Introduzione a Genesi del diritto penale (1791), Milano 1996, pp. 93-98.

[7] Pessina, Letteratura (nt.5), p. 566.

[8] Cfr. G. Tarello, Storia della cultura giuridica moderna. Assolutismo e codificazione del diritto, Bologna 1976, pp. 383-392.

[9] M.A. Cattaneo, I principi dell’illuminismo giuridico penale, in Diritto penale dell’Ottocento. I codici preunitari e il codice Zanardelli, Padova 1999, p. 17.

[10] Isotton, Il Progetto sostituito (nt. 2), p. 129. «Il principio della difesa può apportare, nelle sue rigorose applicazioni, a tragiche conseguenze (si può sacrificare l’innocente per un interesse di difesa) e […] ad applicazioni saltuarie di ingiustizia» (G.F. Falchi, Il pensiero penalistico di G.D. Romagnosi, Padova 1933, p. 48).

[11] «Qual è la regola giustificante l’uso delle pene? La sola Necessità» (Genesi del diritto penale, Pavia 1791 libro II, capo I, § 470). «Col dire, che la pena è necessaria a reprimere il delitto, cosa si suppone egli? Non sembra egli, che dir si voglia, ch’ella sia mezzo efficace ad ottenere un tal fine?» (libro II, capo I, § 473). «L’ Efficacia della pena sull’anima del delinquente è in generale il Risultato de’ rapporti, che passano fra il dolore o minacciato, o irrogato, e l’anima sensibile, e ragionevole, cui s’intima, e si fa sentire […] Dunque l’efficacia della pena, in ultima guisa, risulta in ragion composta della natura, e forza del dolore, e della natura, e forza dell’anima umana assieme combinate» (libro II, capo III, § 496). Siamo ai primi cenni di elaborazione della teoria della spinta criminosa, destinata a rappresentare «una delle più acute intuizioni nella storia del diritto penale» [Ghiringhelli, Introduzione (nt. 6), p. 49, ma in generale cfr. pp. 46-63]. E la «storia, formalmente assente dall’impostazione generale, entra di prepotenza» nel penale [P. Nuvolone, Delitto e pena nel pensiero di G.D. Romagnosi, in «Studi parmensi», 10 (1961), p. 182, ma si vedano pp. 175-183].

[12] Romagnosi, not satisfied by the draft of the law presented by Luosi, guilty, in his opinion, of having limited himself «passare grossolanamente e rapidamente in rivista i delitti e tassarli con una pena qualunque», drew up an alternative «col quale ho riformato, rifuso e aggiunto quanto mi pareva mancare nel progettato codice». The text of Luosi’s commision according to Romagnosi was a «rapsodia dei Codici longobardi, borgognoni, ripuai e un affare tutt’al più di semplice a b c della legislazione penale»; it was unable to represent the “new” and uniqueness that Italian civilization deserved [lettera di Romagnosi del 26 agosto 1806, edita in Tempia,Il progetto (nt. 1), pp. 617-619, in Luzzatto, Giandomenico Romagnosi (nt. 1), pp. 396-398 e in Lettere edite ed inedite di G. D. Romagnosi, a cura di S. Fermi, Milano 1935, lett. n. 63, pp. 96-99].

[13] «Questo manoscritto inedito ad occasione di applicare alla legislazione i principi della Genesi, rappresenta l’espressione del maturato pensiero del Romagnosi; e non è forse senza fondamento il congetturare che per questo egli pensasse più tardi ad un rifacimento della Genesi, nel quale di tutto si sarebbe tenuto il debito conto, onde ne nascesse un vero e proprio trattato di diritto penale» [Luzzatto, Giandomenico Romagnosi (nt. 1), p. 399].

[14] Motivi (nt.3), Appendice al titolo delle pene, All’art. XLII, Sez. Seconda, § 1, f. 29.

[15] Motivi (nt.3), Appendice al titolo delle pene, All’art. XLII, Sez. Seconda, § 1, ff. 29-30.

[16] «L’esacerbazione delle pene si fa a colpi di verghe sul dorso denudato da infliggersi con una data macchina decretata dalla legge. § I. Questa macchina è fatta in guisa che si possa graduare la forza dei colpi a piacere. § II: Presso tutti i Tribunali aventi giurisdizione criminale esiste la macchina del flagello» [Progetto sostituito (nt. 3), tit. VIII, art. 151, p. 162 ed. cit.].

[17] Isotton, Il Progetto sostituito (nt. 2), p. 129.

[18] Cfr. Motivi (nt. 3), Tit. II, All’Art. XI, § 2, f. 13.

[19] Progetto sostituito (nt. 3), tit. V, art. 103, p. 154 ed. cit..

[20] Correctional punishements and those of the local police came afterwards (Progetto del Codice penale pel Regno d’Italia col rapporto che ne contiene i motivi, tit. II, art. 11, inCollezione dei Travagli sul Codice Penale del Regno d’Italia, vol. I, Brescia 1807 [d’ora in poi Progetto (1806)]. See alsoRapporto che contiene i motivi del progetto del Codice penale, in Collezione dei Travagli, pp. 139-150 [d’ora in poi Rapporto]).

[21] Progetto (1806) (nt. 20), art. 12; Progetto sostituito (nt. 3), artt. 104, § 1 e 113, pp. 154 e 156 ed. cit

[22] Progetto (1806) (nt. 20), art. 13; Progetto sostituito (nt. 3), art. 114, pp. 156-157 ed. cit..

[23] Progetto (1806) (nt. 20), art. 16 § 1; Progetto sostituito (nt. 3), art. 116, p. 157 ed. cit..

[24] Progetto (1806) (nt. 20), art. 16 §§ 2-3. «La pena di morte deve riguardarsi per la più terribile e la più imponente nella sua intensità. È perciò ch’ella deve infliggersi senza esacerbazione né addizione di altra pena. Noi abbiamo adottato per l’esecuzione di questa pena il taglio della testa: e sebbene costretti a introdurre una specie di morte esemplare, più imponente cioè nell’apparato, per estendere in qualche modo la gradazione delle pene, col seguire, ma senza ferocia, i gradi di malvagità dei più consumati delinquenti, ci siamo però guardati dall’inasprire coi tormenti l’ultimo fato di chi è pur uomo, quantunque della più turpe scelleraggine macchiato. Vi ha un confine anche nella pena, dove l’umanità arresta la spada della Giustizia. Rimangono per sempre condannati all’esecrazione di chiunque ha palpito di cuore quei feroci Legislatori che con brutale compiacenza gareggiarono nel trovar nuovi modi per esacerbare la pena di morte, e variar lo strazio de’ sciagurati colpevoli» [Rapporto (nt. 20), pp. 151-152].

[25] Cfr. A. Cavanna,Codificazione del diritto italiano e imperialismo giuridico francese nella Milano napoleonica. Giuseppe Luosi e il diritto penale, in Id., Scritti (1968-2002), II, Napoli 2007, pp. 904-918. On the figure of Luosi see Giuseppe Luosi, giurista italiano ed europeo: traduzioni, tradizioni e tradimenti della codificazione a 200 anni dalla traduzione in italiano del Code Napoléon , Modena 2009.

[26] Progetto di codice penale (1801-1802) [from now on Progetto (1801-1802)], edito in A. Cavanna – G. Vanzelli, Il primo progetto di codice penale per la Lombardia napoleonica (1801-1802), Padova 2000, pp. 239-342. Refer to § 35, p. 252.

[27] Progetto (1801-1802) (nt. 26), § 37, p. 252.

[28] The 1791 penal law stated that the death penalty consisteddans la simple privation de la vie, sans qu’il puisse jamais être exercé aucune torture envers les condamnés ( Loi du 25 septembre 1791. Code pénal, parte I, titolo I, art. 2).

[29] On common points between Bentham and the idéologues and the perfect harmony of his philosophy with the expectations and the unrest of the post-termidorian society, see S. Solimano, Verso il Code Napoléon. Il progetto di codice civile di Guy Jean-Baptiste Target (1798-1799), Milano 1998, pp. 69-87. Sull’influenza del pensiero di Bentham nella codificazione penale francese e sulle relative critiche a Beccaria v. pp. 147-157.

[30] G. Vanzelli, Il primo progetto di codice penale per la Lombardia napoleonica (1801-1802), in A. Cavanna – G. Vanzelli, Il primo progetto (nt. 26) p. 59, nt. 123.

[31] On the exact dates of this project, completed in 1802, see, cfr. Solimano, Verso il Code Napoléon (nt. 29), p. 149, nt. 141 and bibliography ivi citata; M. Da Passano, Emendare o intimidire? La codificazione del diritto penale in Francia e in Italia durante la Rivoluzione e l’Impero, Torino 2000, pp. 101-112; Id., I tribunali francesi e il progetto Target. La parte generale, in Codice dei delitti e delle pene pel Regno d’Italia (1811), rist. anast., Padova 2002, pp. XXXV-LXVII; S. Solimano, L’edificazione dell’ordine giuridico napoleonico: il ruolo di Guy Jean-Baptiste Target, in Codice dei delitti e delle pene pel Regno d’Italia, rist. anast., Padova 2002, pp. LXIX-XC; A. Cavanna, Storia del diritto moderno in Europa. Le fonti e il pensiero giuridico, 2, Milano 2005, pp. 590-592.

[32] Solimano, Verso il Code Napoléon (nt. 29), p. 151, nt. 151.

[33] Cfr. M. Da Passano, La pena di morte nella Francia rivoluzionaria e imperiale, in «Materiali per una storia della cultura giuridica», 27 (1997), pp. 379-426.

[34] Sugli omicidj, le ferite, e li furti, e sulle prove, e sull’applicazione delle pene tanto ne’ delitti suddetti, quanto in tutti gli altri delitti (25 febbraio 1804) , in Bollettino delle leggi della Repubblica italiana, pt. I, Milano 1804 pp. 86-112. The 1804 law established that for six crimes, defined as very atrocious (parracide, poisoning, homicide, treason, homocide united with armed robbery or accompanied by robbery, art. 4, p. 88), death must be specialmente exemplary, executed by decapitation, with the head exhibited afterwards «sopra un’asta con cartello indicante nome, cognome e patria del reo; il titolo del delitto, e la qualità di parricidio, latrocinio, o altra che abbia reso atrocissimo l’omicidio, e vi si conserva esposta per le rimanenti ore del giorno» (art. 5, p. 88. Sul punto cfr. C. Danusso, Carlo Bellani: valori etici e pragmatismo di un magistrato al servizio della giustizia, in Ius Mediolani, Milano 1996, pp. 841-842). On the iter compiled on this law see, Vanzelli, Il primo progetto di codice penale (nt. 30), pp. 129-135.

[35] Vanzelli, Il primo progetto di codice penale (nt. 30), p. 135.

[36] Rapporto (nt. 20), pp. 150-151.

[37] Rapporto (nt. 20), p. 150.

[38] Progetto sostituito (nt. 3), art. 116 § 1, p. 157 ed. cit..

[39] Motivi (nt. 3), Tit. II, All’Art. XVI, § 7, f. 17.

[40] Loi du 25 septempre 1791 (nt. 28), parte I, titolo I, art 4.

[41] Motivi (nt. 3), Tit. II, All’Art. XVI, § 7, f. 17.

[42] Motivi (nt. 3), Tit. II, All’Art. XVI, § 7, f. 17.

[43] «La via la più naturale colla quale gli uomini manifestarono sempre la loro detestazione e il loro orrore per qualsiasi o reale o supposto misfatto si fu quella della grandezza e dello spavento dei supplici. Non istà in mano del legislatore il modellare i sentimenti naturali come a lui piace. Bisogna guardarsi che una malintesa dolcezza non li seduca suo mal grado, e non renda le sue leggi ludibrio del robusto e intraprendente malfattore» [Motivi (nt. 3), Tit. II, All’Art. XVI, § 7, f. 17].

[44] «Se parliamo delle pene che si applicano esse devono essere attinte non dai pregiudizi della moda o da una vaga e mal definita premura di dolcezza […], bensì dalla cognizione solida delle cagioni del delitto, della sensibilità, delle abitudini e del temperamento comune dell’azione a cui si danno le leggi […]. Se parlassi ad uomo meno superiore dell’E.V. io dovrei temere di naufragare contro i pregiudici della moda che infetta anche le leggi penali, le quali non debbono avere altra norma che la necessità della cosa, necessità che delude tutte le zerbinerie dei piccoli legislatori e colla forza irrefragabile dell’esperienza costringe quel governo che si lasciò sedurre da loro ad una vergognosa resipiscenza quasi sempre peggiore delle cattive leggi che adottarono» [ Lettera 26 agosto 1806, Corrispondenza Romagnosi-Luosi, in Luzzato, Giandomenico Romagnosi (nt. 1), p. 397].

[45] Motivi (nt. 3), Tit. II, All’Art. XVI, § 7, ff. 17-18.

[46] Dezza, Il codice (nt. 1), p. 159, for an overview see, pp. 140-178.

[47] A. Cavanna, Il Codice penale napoleonico. Qualche considerazione generalissima, in Id., Scritti (nt. 25), p. 1225.

[48] Codice generale sopra i delitti e le pene , Vienna-Rovereto 1787, parte I, cap. II, § 32 e parte II, cap. II, § 11.

[49] Codice penale universale austriaco , Milano 1815, parte I, sez. I, capo II, § 20 e parte II, sez. I, capo II, § 16.

[50] Compare with La ‘magnifica ossessione’. Il sistema delle pene nel codice giuseppino:le contraddizioni di un sistema ‘illuminato’, in Codice generale austriaco dei delitti e delle pene (1787), rist. anast., Padova 2005, pp. CLXIII-CLXVIII.

[51] If in Dei delitti e delle pene Beccaria flawlessly sustained equality of punishments for all subjects without distinction (C. Beccaria, Dei delitti e delle pene, Edizione nazionale delle Opere di Cesare Beccaria, diretta da L. Firpo e G. Francioni, Milano 1984, § XXI, pp. 73-75), twenty years later, in his Brevi riflessioni intorno al Codice generale sopra i delitti e le pene, he urged to consider the differences of social class when imposing a political sanction: «si deve avere moltissimo riguardo alla condizione delle persone, perché il bastone che può correggere un facchino, avvilisce e annienta un nobile, un onesto negoziante, e qualunque civile persona, e involge tutta la loro famiglia nella più luttuosa ignominia» (C. Beccaria,Brevi riflessioni intorno al Codice generale sopra i delitti e le pene, per ciò che risguarda i delitti politici, in C. Cantu’, Beccaria e il diritto penale, Firenze 1862, Appendice, p. 350).

[52] Luigi Villa, the attorney general and tax lawyer who developed a project for the adaptation of the Josephine code of 1787 so that it could enter into force in the territories of Lombardia, sustained that if inflicted in private, the blows could be saved among the «rimedi correttori». Only in the case – added Villa – where the possibility of a revision of the charge of the offender and therefore a possible social recovery was ruled out in advance, was it possible to keep the flogging public. Further caution consisted of limiting the number of blows, in containing the number to fifty for men and thirty for women, not because of abstract evaluation of principles, but in consideration of the complex physical structure of the Lombards, who would not have been able to support more without seriously risking their health. (L. Villa, Originale codice delle Leggi Criminali e Politiche rassegnato al R. Governo dal Procuratore Generale della Camera Ligi Villa nel 1787 7 Giugno , edito in P. Rondini, Il progetto di codice penale per la Lombardia austriaca di Luigi Villa [1787]. Pietra scartata o testata d’angolo?, Padova 2006, p. 286. See also, pp. 121-122 and in particular nt. 169).

[53] The reference is from my essay, Nella disuguaglianza la giustizia. Pietro Mantegazza e il codice penale austriaco (1816), Milano 2002, pp. 96-111.

[54] Progetto sostituito (nt. 3), art. 115, p. 157 ed. cit.

[55] Progetto sostituito (nt. 3), art. 154, p. 162 ed. cit.

[56] Progetto sostituito (nt. 3), art. 155, p. 162 ed. cit.

[57] Progetto sostituito (nt. 3)., artt. 150-153, p. 162 ed. cit..

[58] Progetto sostituito (nt. 3), artt. 156-159, pp. 163-164 ed. cit..

[59] Motivi (nt. 3), Tit. II, All’Art. XLII, Sez. Prima, § 7, f. 26.

[60] Motivi (nt. 3), Tit. II, All’Art. XLII, Sez. Seconda, § 1. f. 30

[61] Motivi (nt. 3), Tit. II, All’Art. XLII, Sez. Seconda, § 2, f. 30.

[62] Motivi (nt. 3), Tit. II, All’Art. XLII, Sez. Seconda, § 3, f. 31.

[63] Cfr. G.P. Massetto, Aspetti della prassi penalistica lombarda nell’età delle riforme: il ruolo del Senato milanese, in Id., Saggi di storia del diritto penale lombardo (Secc. XVI-XVIII), Milano 1994, pp. 365-368.

[64] Motivi (nt. 3), Tit. II, All’Art. XLII, Sez. Seconda, § 3, f. 31.

[65] Motivi (nt. 3), Tit. II, All’Art. XLII, Sez. Seconda, § 2, f. 30.

[66] Motivi (nt. 3), Tit. II, All’Art. XLII, Sez. Seconda, § 4, f. 31.

[67] Motivi (nt. 3), Tit. II, All’Art. XLII, Sez. Seconda, § 5, f. 32.

[68] Motivi (nt. 3), Tit. II, All’Art. XLII, Sez. Seconda, § 6, f. 33.

[69] Motivi (nt. 3), Tit. II, All’Art. XLII, Sez. Seconda, § 6, f. 33.

[70] Some examples, the perpendicular boards were five feet long and were about seven feet away from each other. The board on which the offender lay down on was half a foot below the machine and so on [Motivi (nt. 3), Tit. II, All’Art. XLII, Sez. Seconda, § 6, f. 33].

[71] «Affinché poi nel discendere non oltrepassi la perpendicolare e faccia solamente la metà dell’oscillazione, senza di che egli tenterebbe anche di infrangere le verghe, si contrapponga alla direzione della perpendicolare un macigno, o grosso tronco fitto in terra contro il quale vada a sbattere il detto vette discendendo, e rimbalzi tosto. Acciocché poi il movimento sia più regolare, e intervenga il meno d’arbitrio possibile, si costruisca a fianco del detto vette un congegno di due legni alti un piede circa più della macchina, framezzo a’ quali giri una carrucola. Una corda legata all’estremità del globo o bastone di ferro passi per questa carrucola. L’esecutore mediante questa corda alza il detto vette fin dove può giungere e lo lascia cadere tutto di un tratto. Il corpo del condannato non dovrà mai avere il capo volto verso la parte dalla quale si dà moto alla macchina» [Motivi (nt. 3), Tit. II, All’Art. XLII, Sez. Seconda, § 6, ff. 33-34].

[72] Motivi (nt. 3), Tit. II, All’Art. XLII, Sez. Seconda, § 8, f. 34.

[73] Motivi (nt. 3), Tit. II, All’Art. XLII, Sez. Seconda, § 8, f. 36.

[74] Motivi (nt. 3), Tit. II, All’Art. XLII, Sez. Seconda, § 9, f. 37.

[75] Motivi (nt. 3), Tit. II, All’Art. XLII, Sez. Seconda, § 9, f. 37.

[76] Motivi (nt. 3), Tit. II, All’Art. XLII, Sez. Seconda, § 9, f. 37.

[77] Motivi (nt. 3), Tit. II, All’Art. XLII, Sez. Seconda, § 8, f. 36.

[78] F. Kafka, Nella colonia penale [1914], in Racconti, ed Mondatori, Meridiani Collezione, Milano 2006, pp. 285-318.